.


SCI LIBRARY

Arguments Against Land Value Taxation

George S. Gerber



[Excerpted from a report, A Two-Rate Real Property Tax System, prepared by the Temporary State Commission on The Real Property Tax, April, 1986]


The arguments in Support of land value taxation are numerous and appealing. Nevertheless, uncertainties regarding the merits of this form of taxation have been expressed.

A. Economic Arguments Against Land Value Taxation

  1. Most Economists Have Expressed Opposition to Land Value Taxation. Although a significant number of economists are in favor of land value taxation, the majority of economists have expressed negative, mixed, non-committal, or tentative opinions to the use of land as a tax base, especially in the total manner advocated by Henry George. The space limitations of this report prevent presentation of their individual views.

    a. Those Opposed to the Theory


    J.B. Clark in Distribution of Wealth (1899) disputes the Georgist classical division of economic inputs into the categories of land, labor and capital. Clark eliminates land as a category on the basis that all input factors alike have marginal products, so the laws of production are symmetrical. Therefore, "rent" is not set apart as a "residual" due to "differential" fertility, location, and other qualities. Since land is productive too, land rent is not "surplus" but, rather payment for a productive input. Such payment is a real and legitimate social cost, i.e., the opportunity cost of taking land from the best alternative use. Philip Wicksteed parallels Clark by postulating that all resources are fixed. Supply merely reflects a demand for those already possessing resources. Laws of distribution are symmetrical and rent is erased. There is no surplus because land is a variable," i.e., any individual can have as much land as he wishes, if he can pay the price.

    Vilfredo Pareto (1897) conceptualizes "transfer rent" as a surplus above opportunity cost, which any factor may earn as well as land. This is at variance with George's classical concept that human effort constitutes a sacrifice of leisure, comfort and safety, while land is a gift of nature.

    Alvin Johnson (1902) further develops the "transfer rent" concept, arguing that land is mobile economically among competing uses and therefore yields no more "transfer rent" than other factors.

    Alfred Marshall, Joan Robinson and Hubert Henderson distinguish social viewpoint from that of the individual and social distribution theory from exchange theory. Robinson, for example, argues that from the point of view of society, land is provided free and the whole rent is a surplus and none of it is a social cost.

    On the other hand, Frank Knight and George Stigler (1947) combine the individual and social viewpoints in arguing that a cost to one is a cost to all. Opportunity cost is social costs and there is no basis from distinguishing land from capital. Land is merely investment like any other and competition keeps the returns down to market level.

    Milton Friedman following the concepts of Knight and Pareto, imputes rents to everything and everyone. Frank A. Fetter likewise criticizes Ricardian rent, denying any distinction between land and capital in the vein of Clark.

    b. Those Opposed on the Grounds of Applied Economics


    Real estate economists, such as R. T. Ely, merge land with capital on practical business grounds. Richard Ratcliff (1950) argues that net income can not be split between land and capital.

    Henry C. Carey (1840) theorizes that land speculators make no more on their investment than other investors and hence there was no surplus. This concept is repeated by Shannon and Bodfish (1929), who indicate that since land speculation returns were no more than returns on other investments during the 1920's, no differential tax was justified. Economic surplus should be redefined from economic rent to the income received from buying and selling rents capitalized into land titles. Thus rent, rather than being only a surplus over opportunity costs, is actually a surplus over a normal return on the historical purchase price of the land, whereas for Ricardo and George land value was the whole surplus above zero. Since land is supplied by nature, they viewed social issues from a social viewpoint.

    Willford King (1921,24) writes that capital itself yields no profit from its costs were it not for the rise in land values, i.e., the speculative increase on land yields a return to capital.

    Frank Knight (1953) develops J. B. Clark's doctrine of vested interest acquired by innocent purchasers of land at advanced prices, a doctrine shared by Francis A. Walker, J. S. Mill and others to the effect that regardless of the origins of rent, since society has underwritten the purchase contract it would destroy confidence in contracts to do otherwise. Thus, land is a moral equivalent of man made capital.

    c. Those Opposed on Collectivist Grounds


    Karl Marx (1867) merges land rent with capital and its "mode of production". Marx subordinates land to capital, which seizes all surpluses however generated, even though the supply is elastic.

    Charles Spahr (1891) sees land value produced not by all men, but by certain groups collectively. All wealth is private, both land and capital.

    d. Those Arguing an Inelastic Supply of Capital


    T. S. Adams (1916), H. J. Davenport (1917) and E. R. A. Seligman (1916) argues that if taxes borne by capital lower the after return on capital, they divert investment into land until prices rise, equalizing the return on all investments. Thus, the new owner may buy clear of land taxes, but he is indirectly taxed by taxes on capital which lower the capitalization rate and raise the price of land. An old tax is a good tax, because the market adjusts to it and that a change has to injure someone.

    Jens Jensen (1931), assumes that the supply of capital is fixed, believing that a property tax on producer's goods must therefore rest on the owners of capital in general. Ragnar Frisch (1939) , attacked the concept of taxing land to meet the deficits of marginalist pricing with decreasing costs.

    Jacob Stockfisch (1956,57) and Earl Rolph (1954) follow the doctrine of Adams, Spahr and Seligman in rationalizing the taxation of capital. Mason Gaffney (1971) argues that the property tax is a progressive one on fixed capital, which in most respects is superior to land as a tax base.

    e. Those Claiming Social Functions of Land Speculation


    Richard T. Ely advances the theory of "ripening costs" to explain the function of land speculation. Holding land idle until a rise in value performs a social service, i.e., preventing land from premature under-improvement, while it ripens into a higher use. The holding cost -- the unrealized latent rents -- is the cost of ripening. Land taxes would force premature use at less than optimal intensity. He further denies that land supply is "fixed". Higher price, he argues, creates more man made supply. He believes that capital improvements, land use conversions, migrations, discoveries and substitutions of capital for land actually increase land supply.

    Donald Shoup (1970), Peter Mieszkowski (1970) Roger Smith (1979) and Louis Rose (1971) follow Ely's premises by suggesting that land taxes motivate premature conversion. John Krutilla applies Ely's doctrine to preemption of scenic resources, whereas Orris Herfindhal (1974) sees mineral rents as a return of discovery costs. J. B. Clark (1899), H. P. Davenport (1917) and B. H. Hibbard (1930) argue that land taxation inhibits "rent-seeking" behavior in the form of development of frontiers that were otherwise sub-marginal. Alvin S. Johnson (1914) finds the same effect in cities, i.e., unearned increments, lead men to build in anticipation of future demands. H. J. Davenport believed that land taxes would encourage mining, looting and abandonment of erosive soils.

    F. Y. Edgeworth (1906) writes that land taxes would restrict building profits to the extent that it would deter building and would hamper raising money on security of the premises.

    f. Those Viewing Land Taxation as an Incentive to Overcrowding Central Cities


    Alfred Marshall and Leonard Darwin (1907) see land taxation as resulting in overcrowding of central cities. Edwin Cannan (1907) defends taxing buildings on the grounds that they increase local public costs in proportion to building value. Buildings receive more services in large cities than small. Untaxing them would subsidize congestion in central cities, thus, destroying them. Fiscal sharing more than physical congestion concerns Colin Clark who suggests the necessity of pooling tax revenues at higher levels of government, rather than taxing purely at a local level.

    g. Those Questioning the Adequacy of Land as a Tax Base


    Charles Spahr (1891) and later E. R. A. Seligman (1895) write that marginal communities have little land value and hence no land value tax base. This was based on the belief that taxes on capital are borne by capital. If local capital taxes come instead of land rents, then a direct tax on land is simply a more efficient way of tapping the taxable surplus, which cannot exceed rent anyway.

    Other economists likewise question land's adequacy as a tax base. Ernest Kurnow (1959, 1960 and 1961), Mason Gaffney (1970) Jens Jensen (1931), John A. Zangerle (1927) all point out that land taxes are capitalized, that the value of capital has to remain at cost of production and, therefore, capital is able to yield enormous revenue as compared with land.

    h. Those Opposed on the Ground it is a Scheme for Wider Distribution of Landownership


    Alvin S. Johnson (1914), preceded by Charles Spahr (1891) and E. R. A. Seligman (1895), see the land value tax as a device for despoiling the middle and lower classes because they own most of urban and farm land. Later economic critics argue similarly that any property tax, including land value tax, is regressive.


  2. Land Value Taxation Could Alter the Market Allocation of Land and Construction Resources Away from the Competitive "Ideal". The argument that a shift from the present real property tax to land value taxation could distort the real estate market is predicated upon the fact that a land value tax is not an ad valorem or proportional tax on the entire real estate asset. A land value tax constitutes a higher percentage of the value of land-intensive real estate as compared with real estate with above average improvements to land ratios. The essence of the arguments in favor of land value taxation is that real property taxes would not be increased by more capital-intensive development of sites, since land value alone rather than the land and buildings together forms the base of the tax. It follows that land value taxation would discourage land-intensive urban uses such as parking lots, low rise buildings, obsolete structures and the like. Conversely, it would tend to encourage capital-intensive uses such as high rise structures and newer buildings.

    a. Neutrality of the Present Real Property Tax


    Unlike a land value tax, the present real property tax is an ad valorem tax on the entire real estate asset. Apart from the distortions that occur due to faulty assessment procedures, which could occur under land value taxation as well, the tax burden is proportional to the value of the asset taxed. A proportional tax is neutral with respect to investment decisions, since taxes are the same percentage of value of the asset regardless of what is done with it. Thus, in the case of real estate, the amount of property taxes varies as a constant proportion of value depending upon on how expensive and well maintained the improvement is. Conversely, a land value tax would not be proportional and would decrease as a percentage of property value and income as the parcel is more extensively improved. Hence, theoretically, there would be a stimulus to the development of more capital-intensive uses.

    However, the argument that an ad valorem tax is neutral with regard to real estate investment applies only to the alternatives within the general area of real estate investment. It does not mean that real property taxes have no allocative effects on investment alternatives when considering all possible uses of investment funds. Any such specialized tax, can be expected to reduce the taxable asset's relative share of total investible funds. However, given the assumption that a fixed sum of money is to be raised through some type of real property tax, a proportional tax levied at equal rates of a total asset value on every parcel of private real property is neutral in its effect upon investment decisions as among various alternative types of real estate investments. That is, no matter how a person chooses to develop his property, real property taxes would always represent the same percentage of the resulting real estate asset value. Thus, he cannot reduce his relative tax burden by choosing certain types of uses over others.

    b. An Ad Valorem Land Tax Is Not Neutral


    It is argued that a land value tax is a proportional ad valorem tax on land and thus neutral as to its effect on land uses. However, the real estate investment decision is one of land development. This is true even if a person is investing in vacant land. Land can only be productive if used and its current and potential productivity are determined by improvements that are, or will be made upon it. Thus, real estate investment decisions are decisions with regard to land development, its nature, and its timing. Viewed thusly, land ownership is only part of the entire process. This is particularly true in American real estate practice where landowner, developer and owner of the improvement are frequently the same person.