Our Natural Rights
Harry Pollard
[Reprinted from The Good Society, May 1983]
Let's assume that we are the island castaways. We have recognized the
fact of our unique individuality and we appreciate our similarities.
Urged by the profitability of cooperation, we are obliged to search
out the extent and limits of our individual rights. The implicit
contracts, or negative understandings, such as 'we won't kill, maim,
or otherwise injure each other' have already been accepted, or our
conference would be stillborn.
It is likely that our first concern will be to make the implicit
contracts into explicit contracts. These are protective agreements and
include the idea of enforcement via penalty. If such protective
contracts sound like laws, they should. Though contracts are
individually agreed, people can easily contract in concert for their
mutual protection.
Once we feel safe, we can look to the more positive advantages of
cooperation. As we make our claims, it becomes apparent that every
right we claim is actually an assertion of ownership, 'what is mine
and what is thine'. We are trying to establish what belongs to whom.
However, we need not study every instance of property right. Instead,
we may use the conclusions of the classical political economists. They
separated everything in their universe into three classes -- people,
natural resources, and their products.[1] We may conveniently examine
each in turn.
The aspect of people that is our specific concern is exertion.
Exertion is the external manifestation of humanity. How you act and
what you do is a resultant of all that goes to make you a person.
Meaningful Exertion
Yet, exertion is not always the same. Some is more significant. We
may discard the less important by giving our attention only to
exertion whose result is measurable in the market place. (Sand castles
and mud pies may be artistic, clever and even socially redeeming, but
they are likely also to be both ephemeral and unmarketable.)
So, the essential characteristic of this concept named 'Labor' is
meaningful exertion and this will become the first focal point
of our quest for 'rights', or 'warranted claims'.
Exertion connects each person to the outside world. A favorite,
though rather weak, assertion of libertarians is "I own myself".
It would seem that 'I' is 'myself'. If 'myself' means me in the
corporeal sense, it seems unfair to point out that 'myself' is a
nuisance that no-one would volunteer to own. 'Myself' (the body)
requires attention or it dies. It needs sustenance, care and a place
to sleep, or it may fall prey to ills, agues and injury. At times,
'myself' seems to cost rather more than it is worth.
A slaveowner cares little about the slaves he 'owns'. After all, what
could be more ridiculous than to own people. Bodies come with needs
and requirements -- and occasionally with dangerous inclinations.
Bodies must be confined, perhaps manacled, certainly guarded, probably
punished, sometimes chased. Ownership of bodies is a headache to be
avoided. Although leg-irons may ensure a reluctant cooperation, they
weigh as heavy on production as on the captive.
At the slave auction, the slave-owner does not buy a body. Rather
does he try to acquire the capacity of a mind and body meaningfully
to exert. A slave's attraction rests not in what he is, but in
what he can do. Profit builds not with the body count, but with
effective expropriation of the body's effort.
When the 'meaningful exertion' of a slave can be appropriated without
need to secure, protect and discipline him, slavery becomes markedly
more attractive. That is why it is so prevalent in the modern
world.[2]
Who Claims Exertion?
Exertion is the external manifestation of each person. So, in our
free community, to whom does it belong? Who may assert a right, a
'warranted claim' to it? It probably requires a less than profound
philosophical insight to award ownership of exertion to the one who
exerts.
But, philosophy is buttressed by an intrusive pragmatism. Exertion is
a drag. The mind grows weary and the muscles suffer only so many
contractions before they ache. The one who exerts is also the one who
tires, who drops from fatigue, who requires rest to repair and renew.
It is not without reason that 'we seek to satisfy our desires with the
least exertion'.
We are also pressed by 'unlimited desires', but we find their
satisfaction is married to exertion. Although exertion is not
enthusiastically sought after, we must play out the scene. But, we act
only as a means to receive. A successful alien claim to our exertion
will promptly end the effort. In our free community, exertion will
occur only when Labor's claim to it is clearly accepted.
However, libertarians unhappy with the self-ownership argument should
note the Von Mises assertion, "Ownership means full control of
the services that can be derived from a good". Perhaps it could
be said that when you own your exertion (service) - that establishes
your ownership of you.[3]
Political economy is a social science. Scratching my back is not
within its province. But, if I scratch your back, the action has
become 'social'. It is properly part of the study. Yet, the service
would remain unperformed if you failed to agree that the exertion is
mine. Should you not concede that the scratching (exertion) is mine,
your back will be left to itch. Indeed, if you do not contractually
accept my complete 'right' to the exertion, it will not enter the
market.[4] The performance of a service provides transitory
satisfaction. Your itch has been treated. You are the direct
beneficiary of the exertion. However, you may also enjoy my exertion
at secondhand?
For example, my exertion may be used, not to provide you with an
immediate service, but to bake for you a cake. When you buy the cake
from me, you are receiving (in a sense) my congealed exertion, given
substance by this material product. The question again arises. How may
we establish the right to trade the cake?
The argument for the right to one's exertion applies also to the
right to the products of exertion. Just as exertion would not exist
without a person, so also would not the product. The exertion is
traded for the product. Labor may satisfy another's desire directly
with service, or indirectly with a material construct. The grounds for
yielding ownership of exertion to the exerter also support ownership
of the product by he whose exertion creates it.
Exertion will not be applied if ownership of its results is denied.
This is the problem faced by a voluntary socialist collective. As Man
'seeks to satisfy his desires with the least exertion' any member of
the collective who receives more exertion than he gives will
enthusiastically commend the arrangement. But better producers, who
lose exertion to equal shares' will tend to withdraw. As average
production falls with the loss of the more productive, the collective
will usually fail -- unless coercive restraints are introduced.
A voluntary collective can prosper and remain free when its members
are indifferent to material returns. Psychological rewards may take
their place, such as a the warm sense of belonging to a collective
family or satisfaction from an active commitment to a religious or
philosophical belief or even, perhaps, the exciting attention of a
charismatic leader.
However, on the island our association rests on personal contract, so
our first imperative was to determine warranted claims. We should feel
rather content with the results of our heavy session, for we seem
clearly to have confirmed a person's right to his exertion (Labor) and
to the products of his exertion (Capital and Wealth). In each case,
the creation belongs to the creator. Which leaves to be settled only
the right to natural resources -- the ownership of the island.
And there's the rub, for we are about to run headlong into the arms
of another Creator! Tomorrow's parley is likely to take us on another
long day's journey into 'right'!
NOTES
- 'Political Economy' is a
social science. Indeed, 'political' refers to gatherings of
people, and 'economy' is a word for organization, or system.
Interaction between people means exchange and the marketplace.
Also, because exchanging requires time, it implies production that
is not immediately consumed. Those products still involved in the
process of production and exchange are called Capital, while those
in the hands of the final consumer are called Wealth. In the view
of classical political economy, all things fall into one or the
other of four mutually exclusive classifications, People (Labor),
Natural Resources (Land), and their products (Capital and Wealth).
- A convenient measure of your
'enslavement' is the percentage of your exertion which is taken
without compensation. However, slavery is not determined by the
amount of expropriation, but by its fact. If 1% of a person's
exertion is taken non-contractually, he is enslaved. The
house-slave enjoying a cot inside the mansion was not less a
chattel than the field slave sleeping on an earthen floor.
- Economic classicists including
both Adam Smith and Henry George have suggested that exchange is
really the trading of exertions. George further pointed out (SPE
p. 497) that the value of one's exertion is subjective and
therefore difficult to use as a common measure. Hence, in the
marketplace, it is usual to compare products -- the results of
exertion.
- Time is also a factor. One
exerts only because desires are expected to be satisfied. If this
reward is delayed, Labor demands compensation. Thus is born
'Interest' -- the reward for 'delay of satisfaction'.
|