Tom L. Johnson:
A Personal Study in Civic Ethics
Louis F. Post
[Reprinted from The Freeman, January, 1943]
With the publication of this article THE
FREEMAN inaugurates an "Old Timers Series," in
which will be reprinted from time to time articles dealing with
the speeches, writings and activities of pioneers in the
Georgist movement as chronicled by journals of liberal thought
in America around the turn of the century and in the years
immediately following.
The initial article, by LOUIS F. POST, brilliant journalist and
stout defender of human rights, appeared first in the Christmas,
1901, number of The Mirror, sparkling St. Louis
periodical of which William Marion Reedy, forthright champion of
economic freedom, was editor. It was reprinted in The Public,
a Single Tax weekly edited by Mr. Post himself, in the issue of
February 8,1902. It tells a fascinating story of the coming of
economic enlightenment to Tom L. Johnson, one of the most
colorful figures in the earlier days of Georgism.
It is our thought that these articles will awaken stirring
memories in the hearts and minds of those veteran Georgists who
are still carrying on the good fight, as it is our confident
belief that the younger generation will find in them abundant
evidence that those qualities of flaming zeal, brilliant
dissertation, courage of conviction, unflagging determination
and untiring effort in the cause of civic righteousness, are by
no means peculiar to the crusaders of their own day and age.
There were giants in those days.
|
A group of enthusiasts met in New York 15 years ago to consult about
bringing into practical politics what is now known as Henry George's
single tax reform. One was the late Father McGlynn, the "soggarth
aroon," or beloved priest, of St. Stephen's Roman Catholic
parish, a notable man in New York even then. The most notable person
present, however, was Henry George. He not only represented especially
the cause which had brought about the meeting, but he had already
achieved an international reputation. Three months later, as candidate
for mayor upon a platform indorsing his cause, and after a campaign in
which this cause was the sole issue, he polled 68,000 votes, being
second in a triangular contest between himself, Abram S. Hewitt, who
was elected, and Theodore Roosevelt, now president. Whether or not
this campaign was in any wise due to the meeting mentioned above, that
meeting served, at all events, to introduce to the single tax
movement, and thereby to the political world, an obscure western
millionaire, who, no longer obscure, but known throughout the country
as Tom L. Johnson, has ever since been an unwavering supporter, as he
is now the most conspicuous promoter, of the cause he then first
publicly espoused.
Brought actively into politics by fidelity to this cause, Johnson has
developed into a political leader of originality, skill, popularity
and expanding influence, who interests himself in broad political
principles instead of wire pulling, and supports or opposes men with
reference only to their attitude toward public measures. Yet, until
1886, he had acquired no experience in general politics, nor taken
more than a bare business interest in political affairs.
His abilities had been devoted, from his youth up, to making a
fortune. In this he had so far succeeded as to have advanced from a
penniless boy, son of an impoverished Confederate officer, at the
close of the civil war, to the financial grade of a millionaire while
still under 35 years of age. His business success had not been
achieved by laboriously and penuriously piling dollar upon dollar. The
palaver about the magic of industry and thrift, so much in vogue in
his boyhood, had never deceived him. He did, indeed, work hard; but
not at what he could hire cheaper men to do as well. He did cultivate
habits of thrift; but not of the penurious kind. He did use judgment,
foresight, skill, and all the other industrial virtues; but these were
not the foundation of his fortune. His fortune, like all other stable
fortunes, rests upon monopoly. From the hour when as a newsboy he
worked a railway paper route for which he had shrewdly secured the
exclusive privilege, until a generation later, when he withdrew from
business to devote himself to the cause Henry George bequeathed him,
every business enterprise into which he embarked was bottomed upon and
buttressed by legal privilege.
Johnson had early realized that this is imperative. He knew that the
three requisites of business success are, first, monopoly, second,
monopoly, and third, monopoly. He saw that in so far as the industrial
virtues play a part in fortune-making at all, it is much more in
monopolizing what people need than in producing what they want. These
intimate relations of monopoly to business success were with him as
with all successful business men, mere common places of business
theory and practice. He had given no consideration, however, to the
subject in its ethical and broadly political aspects. Getting a
fortune without getting into jail had seemed to him, as it seems to
most energetic men of this commercial era, the one great object of
life.
But Johnson's better mind awakened. His nightmare visions of piled-up
dollars, pyramid after pyramid in vanishing perspective, were
dispelled, and great realities burst upon his moral consciousness. The
circumstances of his awakening, how in a railroad car he was misled by
the title of Henry George's "Social Problems" into supposing
it a trashy essay on marriage and divorce, and refused therefore to
look into it; how the train conductor enlightened him on that point
and advised his reading the book; how he did read it, and how his
interest grew; how upon finding in this book a reference to "Progress
and Poverty," he bought and read that; how completely he fell
under the sway of this greatest of George's books, yet, fearing that
his mind, then untrained in abstract reasoning, might have been
tricked by fallacies, how he solicited the opinion of his lawyer and
his lawyer pronounced the reasoning flawless but the premises false;
how this clinched his conversion, because, though from lack of
academic culture he was timid as to the logic of the book, he had, as
an experienced business man, already acknowledged the truth of its
premises; and how at the end he converted his lawyer, when the latter
undertook to argue him out of his waywardness -- this has all been
told before in interesting detail. What concerns the present subject
is the fact that Johnson was startled by seeing in George's book the
commonplace principles of business translated into terms of political
economy and civic morality. He now realized that whatever of wealth
any man wins as a monopolist, other men must lose as productive
workers.
The great economic truth that had been disclosed was the elemental
economic power of the monopoly of land. Other monopolies there are,
but without this the others could not flourish, and if they were
abolished it would absorb their strength. Railroad monopoly, for
instance, Johnson now recognized as land monopoly, its power
consisting in exclusive rights of way and in terminal points. Street
car monopoly, city service monopolies of all kinds, are also at bottom
land monopolies, for it is by their exclusive rights of way over land
that they control conditions of traffic. And in ordinary so-called
competitive industry, whatever monopoly exists, the monopoly of
patents alone excepted, has its roots in land monopoly. Moreover, if
every monopoly except that of land were abolished, the financial
benefits would go ultimately to monopolists of land. So, as Johnson
saw the matter after his conversion from money-getting ambitions to
humanitarian ideals, the monopoly of monopolies is the monopoly of
land.
He saw also the great moral truth that land monopoly is robbery. To
see this truth he did not need to have been a college fledgling. All
he needed was common sense. Granted that God is no respecter of
persons, and it follows that all men are intended by Him to enjoy
equal rights of usufruct in the earth. This enjoyment the monopoly of
land prohibits. Or, if the idea of a bountiful Creator be considered "unscientific,"
then, granted that Nature yields her stores only to productive labor
(an hypothesis which defies dispute), and it follows, unless righteous
principles be rejected altogether and moral adjustments are to be
referred to the pirates' code of simple might, that there can be no
moral title to products from the earth-which include every consumable
thing -- except it be derived from productive laborers with their free
consent. Inasmuch, then, as monopoly of the earth enables monopolists
to extort from productive laborers part of their earnings, it stands
morally condemned. . .
The truth is that Johnson's awakened conscience looked out upon an
iniquitous social institution. It was not from the machinations of bad
men, but from the development of a bad institution, that industry was
plundered and that society suffered. The immorality to which he awoke,
and out of which he had secured a fortune partly unearned but in which
millions had found only poverty and distress wholly undeserved -- this
immorality was not individual and capable of correction by individual
reform. It was an institutional immorality, which could be corrected
only by institutional reform. The notion that institutional evils can
be put away, like personal evils, by individual abstention, is an
eccentricity of narrow minds. Though every individual but one were to
abstain from monopolizing land, land monopoly would not die out if the
institution were still acknowledged, but would be worse. For the one
unregenerate individual would then monopolize the whole earth, and all
the regenerate would become his submissive serfs. Individuals can no
more alter unjust institutions by declining to profit by them than
they could alter the direction of a stream by not swimming in it.
Institutional wrongs can be remedied only by institutional reforms.
Individual action there must be, of course, for society is composed of
individuals. But it must be cooperative and not segregated individual
action; not the action of the recluse, but that of the citizen. So
Johnson solved his problem in the only way in which it could be
morally and sensibly solved. He decided to devote himself to the
destruction of the institution of land monopoly, by the method
advocated by Henry George and now known as the single tax; and to do
this without regard to its ultimate effect upon his personal fortune,
and without any affectations meanwhile of an impossible consistency
between his private business, in which monopoly was a factor, and his
public work of abolishing monopoly.
He raised his lance not against millionaires nor monopolists, not
against the rich because they are rich nor for the poor because they
are poor; but against the institution of monopoly and for institutions
of justice. The distinction he drew between utilizing monopolies in
business and maintaining the monopoly institution, was sharply
illustrated by him upon the floor of Congress while he was a member.
Congressmen representing the steel trust were struggling for the
protective tariff on steel. Johnson himself was then in the steel
business and his company was a member of the steel trust. He,
therefore, like the others, was getting a tariff "rake-off."
Yet he vigorously opposed the tariff measure. One of the steel trust
congressmen, twitting him in the debate with his connection with the
steel trust, implied that as he was getting part of the plunder he
ought to support the law that secured it. "Gentlemen,"
retorted Johnson, "as a monopolist in the steel business I will
take advantage of the bad laws you pass; but as a member of this
house, I will not help you pass them, and I will try to get them
repealed."
More in detail, and as a private citizen instead of a congressman, he
made the same distinction at a public meeting in New York in 1891. A
questioner in the audience asked him:
"You have just advocated the abolition of land
monopoly, of the tariff monopolies, of the patent monopolies, and of
the street railroad monopolies. Is it not a fact that you have been,
and are now, a shining beneficiary of all these iniquities? And if
you are, how do you reconcile your actions with your professions?"
To that searching question Johnson replied:
"I advocate now and have advocated the abolition of
all these forms of monopoly, and yet I am and have been a
beneficiary of them all. If there is any inconsistency in that it is
not my fault. I preach what I sincerely believe to be the true and
just social condition -- the condition of equal rights, of real
freedom. Yet I must live under such laws and usages as the majority
of the people decree. They say that these monopolies shall exist;
that bread-winning shall be a scramble; that there shall be many
poor among us and comparatively few rich. I do not believe that this
is right, and I am raising my voice wherever possible against it.
But the people will not yet listen. They have different views from
mine, and they hold to them. Now being compelled to live in this
state of things where life is a scramble which the people will not
stop, I am bound to do the best I can for myself. And so I rush in
and grab all the monopolies I can get my hands on, firm in the
purpose, however, to use the wealth so obtained to teach the people
how misguided they are to permit themselves to be robbed in this
way."
That purpose of using his fortune acquired by monopoly to break up
monopoly has been faithfully adhered to. Not as an atonement, not as a
means of satisfying his conscience for having got the fortune through
monopoly. In no sense for personal reasons, but with the same motive
that he gives to this work of his life what is incontestably all his
own. . . .
One such man as Tom L. Johnson, who profits by monopoly and excuses
monopolists, yet denounces the institution of monopoly and makes
relentless war upon it, is worth more to the cause of civic justice
than a host of men who rail at monopolists as wrong doers merely
because they are monopolists, yet allow the institution of monopoly to
go unchallenged, or challenge it without intelligence. The true
principle of civic ethics is that which Johnson exemplifies. It does
not consist in rejecting profits which unjust institutions yield to
the favored or fortunate. So long as social adjustments are such that
those profits cannot be relinquished to the persons who earn them,
justice is served neither by giving them to others nor by rejecting
them altogether. It is not affirmatively ethical to get rid of them;
consequently it is not unethical to keep them. What ethics does demand
is that the beneficiary of such profits shall awaken to the enormity
of the social institution that diverts them from their unidentified
producers, and in his capacity of citizen aid his fellow citizens of
like enlightenment and moral impulse to bring that vicious institution
to an end.
|