Pure poison on land tax
Gavin R. Putland
[22 March, 2009. Reprinted from the Land Values Research Group
website]
... offers the antidote for Sinclair Davidson.
There are many valid arguments which the economic establishment
finds inconvenient but cannot refute, and which it therefore attacks
by obfuscation and diversion. The obfuscators are entitled to the
presumption (although it cannot be true of them all) that they are
not instigators but co-victims, merely teaching what they have been
taught. But that in no way mitigates the damage.
Consider the attack on Steve Keen, a non-establishment
economist who is kicking too many goals for the establishment's
liking, by Rory Robertson of Macquarie Bank. Robertson
ridiculed Keen's focus on
debt-to-GDP
ratios by accusing Keen of “the schoolboy error of
comparing debt to income (a stock to a flow — apples to
oranges)”. Presumably the reader isn't meant to notice
that apples and oranges are both stocks. Even if we ignore that
technicality, the argument that you can't divide a stock by a flow
epitomizes the remoteness of mainstream economists from the real
world. A person of more practical bent, such as a plumber or a motor
mechanic or even an applied mathematician, would know that the ratio
of a stock to a corresponding flow has the units of time and is
related to a real-world time, e.g. the time taken to fill the
bathtub (while the flow replenishes the stock) or to empty the fuel
tank (while the stock sustains the flow). But for the reader who is
in too much of a hurry to notice these things, the combination of
the jargon (“a stock to a flow”), the cliché
(“apples to oranges”) and the cheap insult (“schoolboy
error”) will probably be enough to hose down any interest
in Keen's work. It's a form of censorship, accomplished not by
gagging the speaker but by turning away the audience.
Don't get me wrong: Dr Keen's dire predictions may yet turn out to
be overblown. But if they do, it won't be because he compared a
stock to a flow.
The Georgists — those who would finance government
from the economic rent of land and other non-replicable assets, in
lieu of taxes that penalize production and strangle it with red tape
— can sympathize with Dr Keen, having endured similar
treatment for more than a century. As the “global
financial crisis” deepens, the imperative to put down the
Georgists has become acute, partly because the failure of mainstream
economics has, by default, focused attention on the alternatives,
and partly because an embarrassing number of Georgists predicted the
crisis years ago [1,2,3,4],
while central bankers remained in denial until what couldn't happen
again had just happened again.
So something had to be done about Bryan Kavanagh's article
“Breaking
in on the rent seekers”, which appeared on the back
page of the Age on March 11, saying in part:
The truth is that the public capture of
publicly generated land rent never does harm to society. To the
contrary, it may be dawning on politicians and analysts that the
real estate bubble was the inevitable result of inadequate
land-value capture. They may even consider extending and fortifying
council rates and state land taxes in order to prevent damaging real
estate bubbles from developing again in the future.
The rejoinder, from Prof. Sinclair Davidson of RMIT and
the Institute of Public [sic] Affairs, was headed “Textbook
example is not grounded in earthy reality”. The
edited version in the Age did not mention Kavanagh's
article, but just happened to appear two days later on the same page
(and on
the IPA's website). But Davidson's original
text includes a link to Kavanagh's piece.
Against the Georgist premise that land is fixed in supply,
Davidson writes:
While land is fixed in geographic
terms, land as an economic asset is not. Land, like capital, can be
allocated from one usage to another.
Note the unjustified substitution of allocation for supply. But
this bait-and-switch doesn't solve Davidson's problem, because if
land owners pay a sufficiently heavy holding tax on their land, they
must allocate it productively in order to cover the tax, or sell it
to someone who will. In either case, absentee owners cannot afford
to hold land for purely speculative purposes; they need to attract
paying tenants, and this need improves the bargaining power of
tenants, making rents more affordable. Meanwhile the pressure to
sell land makes it more affordable for prospective buyers.
If capital is taxed in the same way, one can avoid the tax by
destroying the capital (or not creating it in the first place), thus
reducing production. But when land is taxed in this way, one can
only reallocate it, thus increasing production. Therein lies the “free
lunch” whose existence Davidson denies. Therein lies the
distortion in Davidson's claim that land is an input into wealth
creation “just as any other factor of production.”
A uniform land-value tax does not inhibit reallocation of land. A
land-value tax with exemptions does not inhibit reallocation between
non-exempt uses. A stamp duty on conveyancing severely inhibits
reallocation because it taxes a change of ownership rather
than a continuation of ownership. But Davidson, for reasons best
known to himself, complains about land tax instead of stamp duty.
Having switched from supply to allocation, Davidson then switches
back by quoting John Bates Clark against the idea “that
land is fixed in amount...” Giving the reader a second
chance to notice the bait-and-switch is clumsy, especially as it
could have been avoided by presenting the arguments in a different
order, and therefore tends to support the presumption that Davidson
actually believes his own bafflegab. Be that as it may, quoting
Clark was obligatory because his 1899 textbook The
Distribution of Wealth, more than any other, established
the neo-classical doctrine that land is a form of capital, wherefore
the rent of land is a form of interest — or, as Davidson's
title puts it, “There is no such thing as geo-rent”.
Prof. Mason Gaffney [5]
describes Clark's technique
as
follows:
On p.2, the rent of land is merged with
interest “for
reasons that will appear later”. This begins a kind
of “proof by infinite retreat”. The promised
reasons are later put off again to Chapter XXII, which
puts
them off to Chapter XXIV, where they finally disappear in
the fine print of one
of the longest footnotes in history, pp.395–98. Along
the way he repeats his idea that capital is immortal, reprinting
earlier works as chapters. At one point he says rent is interest
because it equals the interest rate times the price of land.
Elsewhere he says unearned increments are really part of the wages
of workers who are also landowners. Device after device is used;
deferral after deferral of promises to treat central matters “later”.
Meantime, however, rent is interest and land is capital throughout
the book.
It's not science (and if you didn't get the joke, look up “proof
by infinite descent”); but it's convenient for those who
wish to undercut the case for a selective tax on land. To that end,
Davidson quotes Clark as saying “The idea that land is
fixed in amount, ..., is really based on an error which one
encounters in economic discussions with wearisome frequency.”
Let us put this quote back
in context
so that we can see what passes for logic in Clark's definitive text:
Let us see how much, in a static study, these distinctions
amount to. That capital, in the aggregate, should be fixed in
amount, is one of the conditions of the static state. This
assumption, moreover, expresses what is true at any one moment in
a dynamic state. The gross amount of capital in the world cannot
be instantly changed, and the rate of interest at this moment is
based on the gross amount existing at this moment. If dynamic
changes were not to occur, the present amount would be the
permanent one, and all capital could be treated, like land, as a
fixed quantity. The idea that land is fixed in amount, and that
capital can be increased at will and to any extent, is really
based on an error which one encounters in economic discussions
with wearisome frequency.
... At any one time, the amount of artificial capital in
existence is as fixed as is the amount of land. Within any short
time it is impossible to increase the general fund of artificial
capital enough to make a perceptible difference in the conditions
of social industry. At any one time we have to deal with a
definite quantity of land, in combination with a definite amount
of capital in artificial forms. Moreover, the distinction between
land and other capital-goods, based on the notion that land cannot
be increased and that other things can be, has obviously no
validity in a static study; for the static assumption itself
precludes all increase of capital.
In short, assume away the problem by supposing a static state,
dismiss the inconvenient reality of a dynamic state by taking a
static snapshot, pretend that what cannot be “instantly
changed” might as well be set in stone, and presto!
— capital is as permanent as land. Then complain because the
belief that land is different from capital keeps popping up with “wearisome
frequency”, and don't mention the possibility that the
reason why it won't go away is that it happens to be true. Does
anyone not smell a hired gun?
Davidson further informs us (in his original
text) that Frank H. Knight “dismissed
the idea of land as an economic asset being fixed in supply as ‘utterly
fallacious’.” Here's that quote in context, in
Risk,
Uncertainty, and Profit (1921),
Pt.II, Ch.V:
The definition given for land to make
it fit the description of a fixed supply — the original and
inexhaustible powers of the soil — is indeed drastic in its
limitation. Later, this dogma of unconditional fixity of supply was
made the basis for the single-tax propaganda. We cannot discuss this
position at length, but must take space to remark quite briefly that
it is utterly fallacious. It should be self-evident that when the
discovery, appropriation, and development of new natural resources
is an open, competitive game, there is unlikely to be any difference
between the returns from resources put to this use and those put to
any other.
Unfortunately this “self-evident” proposition
has nothing to do with whether land is fixed in supply. But the
reader who takes the time to be convinced by it, and who is
sufficiently impressed by its truth (and by his/her ability to
perceive its truth), will, with any luck, fail to notice that it
doesn't prove what it pretends to prove. Another red herring is the
reference to “original and inexhaustible powers of the
soil”. Nowadays the value of land depends more on its
location than on its soil quality; but this in no way contradicts
fixity of supply. The pretense that the definition of land must be
artificially narrowed “to make it fit the description of a
fixed supply” is false and highly prejudicial. (Moreover,
if we indeed define land for economic purposes as the factor
limited in supply, we find that this definition is slightly wider
than the everyday meaning. The Georgist literature of Knight's time
already placed natural resources and “public franchises”
in the same category as land.) Similarly prejudicial are the words “drastic”,
“dogma” and “propaganda” in
varying degrees of proximity to “single-tax”,
the then-fashionable description of the Georgist proposal. It is all
well calculated to bypass the reader's critical faculties at the
expense of the Georgists.
Knight's “self-evident” proposition is
reminiscent of another claim often adduced against Georgists, namely
that the return on land is no higher than the return on other
assets. This too is a red herring. The case for a selective tax on
land does not depend on the premise that the return on land,
relative to its cost of acquisition, is abnormally high. It depends
rather on the fact that the return on an asset that can be privately
produced (capital) is an incentive to produce it, while the return
on an asset that cannot be privately produced (land) is not.
Knight defended and elaborated the Clarkian doctrine that capital
is static. Gaffney [op. cit.]
explains it
this
way:
Capital, unlike land, has a finite life. It depreciates and is
reproduced. That is, it turns over. The reciprocal of turnover is
a period of time, which the Austrians call a “period of
production”. This was anathema to Clark, who wanted to
erase the difference of land and capital by making capital
deathless, like land, and have capital consist of a mystical
essence that could “transmigrate” into land
and explain its value.
Knight took up Clark's anti-Austrian attack with multiplied
vigor. In this context, anti-Austrian means anti-Georgist. ...
... Knight goes so far as to commit the “fallacy of
the disappearing inventory”. According to him, the
existence of capital lets us treat inflow and outflow of goods
through inventories as simultaneous. Likewise we may treat
production and consumption as simultaneous, however long goods are
stored up in inventory... The result of such thinking is to bypass
the whole question of what capital is and does, and, damagingly
for George, to erase a primary distinction of capital from land.
Knight uses the point for this very purpose.
The lost distinction is that capital turns over; it is
continuously being used up and replaced by hiring labour to
produce more. The longer it takes capital to work through the
pipeline, the more capital is required per worker and per unit of
output, and the higher is the ratio of capital to labour. Add to
that, the pipeline itself is capital. Likewise, since pipes occupy
space, the more land is required. To keep the distinction of land
and capital well lost, Clark and Knight were forced to dispute the
Austrian capital theory, which each of them did in their oft-cited
debates with, respectively, Böhm-Bawerk and Hayek. These
celebrated exchanges seem quite tedious and pointless, and even
mystical, until one realizes their essential role in the
imperative to slam the lid on Henry George and his idea of
treating land and capital separately. They were essentially
battles of Anti-Georgists vs. Anti-Marxists.
Davidson, like Knight, knows how to use strong language to soften
up his readers for a weak argument. Before the double
bait-and-switch and the quotes from Clark and Knight, Davidson
writes:
The early Greeks viewed direct tax on
land as the mark of tyranny. So too do modern taxpayers.
He doesn't explain why we shouldn't regard speculatively inflated
land prices, or the compliance costs of income tax, payroll tax and
GST, as marks of tyranny, or why we shouldn't draw the obvious
inference that modern western civilization might be headed the way
of ancient Greece. But this tactic may help to explain why the
geo-rent tax is attributed solely to Henry George without mentioning
its earlier or later proponents. It would be a bit hard for a “free-market”
think-tank like the IPA to accuse Adam Smith [6],
John Stuart Mill [7],
Winston Churchill [8],
Milton Friedman [9] and
William F. Buckley Jr. [10,11]
of advocating “tyranny”. But it's easy to pin
that charge on Henry George because his
free-market credentials, although stronger than those of any
right-wing demagogue, are less well known.
When Davidson finally gets around to presenting his core argument,
it comes down to this:
[N]ature does not yield economic value
easily. At any level of economic activity above hunter-gathering
natural produce must be combined with capital, labour, and
entrepreneurial insight before economic value can be created.
That's half the truth. The other half, which the reader is not
supposed to notice, is that the party who gets the economic value is
not necessarily the one who adds the “capital, labour, and
entrepreneurial insight”. And when the holding tax on land
is too low to offset expected capital gains, why would the owners
bother applying capital, labour and entrepreneurship when they can
simply acquire more land, whose value is increasing due to the
capital, labour and entrepreneurship applied by other
parties on surrounding land?
Davidson's conclusion that a tax on land is a tax on capital or
labour does not follow from any of his earlier assertions. Neither
is it true. From the micro-economic viewpoint, a tax on land does
not rise or fall with the amount of labour or capital applied by the
taxpayer. From the macro-economic viewpoint, the inelasticity of the
supply of land implies that taxes on
capital or labour, together with their deadweight costs, tend to
be shifted onto land. If the same revenue were raised from
taxes levied directly on land, the land owners would actually be
better off because there would be no deadweight. Furthermore, if a
government's revenue is apportioned to land values, that government
has the ability and the incentive to invest in infrastructure that
raises land values for the benefit of the owners. By opposing taxes
on land values, the property lobby and its academic allies frustrate
the funding of projects that would increase returns for property
investors. The hired guns have shot their clients.
* * *
P.S. (March 27): Since this article was posted, Steve Keen
has released a web-friendly version of his recent critique of neo-classical
economics [11a]. He
does not address the conflation of land with capital, but does
address the closely related static-state assumption (which he calls
“the obsession with equilibrium”), saying in
part:
The fallacy that dynamic processes must
be modelled as if the system is in continuous equilibrium through
time is probably the most important reason for the intellectual
failure of neoclassical economics.
References
[1] “By 2007,
Britain and most of the other industrially advanced economies will
be in the throes of frenzied activity in the land market to equal
what happened in 1988/89. Land prices will be near their 18-year
peak, driven by an exponential growth rate, on the verge of the
collapse that will presage the global depression of 2010.”
— Fred Harrison, “The Coming ‘Housing’
Crash”, in F.J. Jones & F. Harrison, The
Chaos Makers (London, Othila Press, 1997).
[2] “The 18-year
cycle in the US and similar cycles in other countries give the
geo-Austrian cycle theory predictive power: the next major bust, 18
years after the 1990 downturn, will be around 2008...”
— Fred E. Foldvary, “The
Business Cycle: a Georgist-Austrian Synthesis”, American
J. of Economics and Sociology 56(4):521–41 (October 1997).
[3] “If the U.S.
economy is shedding jobs,... how does it finance its growing
consumption and rising asset values? By a credit expansion...,
backed by assets whose values are totally dependent on the circular
argument that values will keep increasing. Eventually a major
asset market must collapse, causing a credit contraction and
liquidity loss, which reduces demand for goods and services and
causes other asset markets to collapse, and so on. Worse, as the
members of one economic class go bankrupt, they take down their
creditors, who in turn take down more creditors, and so on, until
most of the population has neither sufficient assets nor sufficient
credit to do business. That's a depression. And the U.S., as the
world's biggest debtor and consumer, cannot sink into depression
without dragging the rest of the world down with it.”
— Gavin R. Putland, letter in the Australian
Financial Review, Sep.10, 2003.
[4] “At the
bursting of each property bubble... the economy has declined into
recession... ...Australians have taken their eyes off the ball. We
began to follow the dictates of the tax regime to play another game
altogether, namely, that of real estate speculation. We have
now inflated the current residential bubble to voluminous
proportions and economic growth is primed to tank into a major
deflation... [T]he next adjustment of Australian interest
rates would more properly be down.” — Bryan Kavanagh,
“Resource
rents hold the property key”, The Age,
Jun.15, 2005.
[5] M. Gaffney,
Neo-classical
Economics as a Strategem against Henry George, printed in
M. Gaffney, F. Harrison, and K. Feder,
The
Corruption of Economics (London: Shepheard-Walwyn,
1994), pp. 29–164.
[6] “Both
ground-rents and the ordinary rent of land are a species of revenue
which the owner, in many cases, enjoys without any care or attention
of his own. Though a part of this revenue should be taken from him
in order to defray the expenses of the state, no discouragement will
thereby be given to any sort of industry. The annual produce of the
land and labour of the society, the real wealth and revenue of the
great body of the people, might be the same after such a tax as
before. Ground-rents and the ordinary rent of land are, therefore,
perhaps, the species of revenue which can best bear to have a
peculiar tax imposed upon them.” — Adam Smith,
The Wealth of Nations,
Bk.V, Ch.2,
Pt.I, Art.I.
[7] “I see no
objection to declaring that the future increment of rent should be
liable to special taxation; in doing which all injustice to the
landlords would be obviated, if the present market-price of their
land were secured to them; since that includes the present value of
all future expectations. With reference to such a tax, perhaps a
safer criterion than either a rise of rents or a rise of the price
of corn, would be a general rise in the price of land. It would be
easy to keep the tax within the amount which would reduce the market
value of land below the original valuation: and up to that point,
whatever the amount of the tax might be, no injustice would be done
to the proprietors. [§6] But whatever may be thought
of the legitimacy of making the State a sharer in all future
increase of rent from natural causes, the existing land-tax (which
in this country unfortunately is very small) ought not to be
regarded as a tax, but as a rent-charge in favour of the public; a
portion of the rent, reserved from the beginning by the State, which
has never belonged to or formed part of the income of the landlords,
and should not therefore be counted to them as part of their
taxation... All who have bought land since the tax existed have
bought it subject to the tax. There is not the smallest pretence for
looking upon it as a payment exacted from the existing race of
landlords. ... The whole of it, therefore, is not
taxation, but a rent-charge, and is as if the state had retained,
not a portion of the rent, but a portion of the land. It is no more
a burthen on the landlord, than the share of one joint tenant is a
burthen on the other.” — John Stuart Mill,
Principles of Political Economy,
Bk.V, Ch.2.
[8] “Roads are
made, streets are made, railway services are improved, electric
light turns night into day, electric trams glide swiftly to and fro,
water is brought from reservoirs a hundred miles off in the
mountains — and all the while the landlord sits still. Every
one of those improvements is effected by the labour and at the cost
of other people. Many of the most important are effected at the cost
of the municipality and of the ratepayers. To not one of those
improvements does the land monopolist, as a land monopolist,
contribute, and yet by every one of them the value of his land is
sensibly enhanced. ... The tax on the increment of land
begins by recognising and franking all past increment. We look only
to the future; and for the future we say only this: that the
community shall be the partner in any further increment above the
present value after all the owner's improvements have been deducted.
We say that the State and the municipality should jointly levy a
toll upon the future unearned increment of the land. A toll of what?
Of the whole? No. Of a half? No. Of a quarter? No. Of a fifth
— that is the proposal of the Budget. And that is robbery,
that is plunder, that is communism and spoliation, that is the
social revolution at last, that is the overturn of civilised
society, that is the end of the world foretold in the Apocalypse!
Such is the increment tax about which so much chatter and outcry are
raised at the present time, and upon which I will say that no more
fair, considerate, or salutary proposal for taxation has ever been
made in the House of Commons.” — Winston Churchill,
speech
delivered at the King's Theatre (Edinburgh) on July 17, 1909,
reported by the Times and reprinted in
Liberalism
and the Social Problem (London: Hodder & Stoughton,
1909).
[9] “In my opinion
the least bad tax is the property tax on the unimproved value of
land, the Henry George argument of many, many years ago.”
— Milton Friedman,
interviewed
by the Times Herald (Norristown, PA), Dec.1, 1978.
[10] From an
interview
with Brian Lamb on Book Notes, C-SPAN, Apr.2-3, 2000:
Caller: I've heard you describe yourself as a Georgist,
a follower of Henry George, but I haven't heard much in having you
promote land value taxation and his theories, and I'm wondering
why that is the case.
William F. Buckley Jr.: It's mostly
because I'm beaten down by my right-wing theorists and
intellectual friends. They always find something wrong with the
Single-Tax idea. What I'm talking about, Mr. Lamb, is Henry George
who said there is infinite capacity to increase capital and to
increase labor, but none to increase land, and since wealth is a
function of how they play against each other, land should be
thought of as common property. The effect of this would be that if
you have a parking lot and the Empire State Building next to it,
the tax on the parking lot should be the same as the tax on the
Empire State Building, because you shouldn't encourage land
speculation. Anyway I've run into tons of situations where I
think the Single-Tax theory would be applicable. We should
remember also this about Henry George: he was sort of co-opted by
the socialists in the 20s and the 30s, but he was not one at all.
Alfred J. Nock's book on him makes that plain. Plus, also, he
believes in only that tax. He believes in zero income tax.
(“Alfred” should be “Albert”.
It is not clear whether the error is Buckley's or the
transcriber's.)
[11] “Henry
George said that the rent of all land ought to be public... I am
sympathetic with that particular analysis.” — William F. Buckley Jr.
on
Firing Line, Public Broadcasting Service, Jan.6, 1980.
[11a] Steve Keen, “Mad,
bad, and dangerous to know”, Real-World
Economics Review, No.49 (Mar.12, 2009), pp.2–7;
republished
in
HTML, Mar.24, 2009.