The Nature of Urban Land
M.A. Qadeer
[Reprinted from the American Journal of Economics
and Sociology,
Vol. 40, No. 2 (April 1981)]
At the time this paper was published, M.A.
Qadeer was on the faculty of the School of Urban and Regional
Planning, Queen's University, Kingston, Canada
|
ABSTRACT. Considerations about land interpose into almost
every aspect of urban life. They may not be the only factor
determining a city's well-being but appropriate land policies
are necessary to bring about prosperity and equity. Contemporary
accounts of the 'urban crisis' and of urban problems
reveal the pervasiveness of land issues. Use of one urban land parcel
has bearing on the usability of neighboring sites, which makes land a
community resource. Urban land may be denned as land used or
expected to be used for urban activities. Its attributes include
location, space, property, clustering, heterogeneity and immobility
and indestructibility. Neo-classical theorists, by stressing
accessibility and ignoring externalities and other attributes of land,
achieved only an unrealistic understanding of it. Most land economists
are institutionalists, their theory encompassing
long-validated concepts about the nature of land.. The neo-Marxian
approach has many points of congruence with the institutionalist one.
Empirically investigated, urban land is found to be different from
economic goods and hence its production, allocation and disposition
must proceed at least like other public goods.
I: LAND, THE BASIS OF HUMAN LIFE
LAND is A HUMAN NECESSITY. Everybody needs some ground to
stand, sit, sleep and walk on. These are the habitational uses of land
without which human life is inconceivable. Land is also needed for
productive activities; agriculture, forestry and mining, the primary
activities, are obviously dependent upon land. The secondary and
tertiary activities, i.e. manufacturing, commerce and
services, use land as the stage of their operations. One way or the
other, land is a basic resource of human life. In modern urban
settings, the significance of land as a resource is all the more
striking.
The contemporary city is the locale of modern industrial society. In
it most of production is carried out and here reside a majority of
consumers, particularly in industrialized societies. The Third World
countries may not be numerically dominated by cities, but there is
increasing concentration of political and economic power in urban
centers. Cities are not merely the places where large numbers of
activities and people have congregated. Their distinguishing
characteristic is a high degree of interrelatedness of activities
resulting in a complex system which is more than the sum of its parts.
In economic terms, it is the agglomeration effect which makes a city a
dynamic center of modern life (1). The division of labor lays ground
for an intricate network of inter-dependencies of activities (2).
Sociologically, the specialization of roles results in formalization
and bureaucratization of social structures. Laws and impersonal rules
become the bases of social order and communications become a cardinal
necessity for smooth functioning of this complex system. Land acquires
an additional role in a city. It acts as a coordinating and
interrelating matrix by relative 'siting' of interrelated activities.
Land is the physical base over which an urban system operates. This
is obvious. What is not so apparent is that to be the base is not a
passive role. The manner in which people and activities are
distributed over land has significant bearing on their efficiency,
economy and welfare. There are two aspects of this process: (i)
proportionality and (ii) pattern of distribution. Relative proportions
of land allocated to housing, shops or industry or open spaces, etc.,
determine the balancing of various activities. More land for housing
might create a shortage of industrial sites which would affect
employment levels and vice versa. Whether a city will have a housing
shortage or job scarcity is partially determined by the amount of land
allocated to corresponding activities. But this is only one of the
ways in which the disposition of land determines the economy and
well-being of an urban system. Equally significant, if not more, is
the pattern of distribution which defines where houses, shops or
offices are located in relation to each other and their mutual
accessibility. A pattern of land use is essentially an expression of
interdependencies of social and economic activities. An appropriate
pattern can facilitate the interrelations and thus lay grounds for an
efficient and productive urban economy; the mismatching of land uses
produces the reverse effects. It is possible that individual parcels
of land may be gainfully used yet the cumulative effect would be
disastrous. Much maligned suburban sprawl is a case in point. This
concern with the interrelatedness of land uses is the raison
d'etre of the city planning profession. From an economic point of
view, urban land is a resource whose allocation must be guided by
criteria of city wide economy and efficiency (3).
The term land in economics has conventionally included improvements
made to it or attached to it. Thus urban land is both a resource and a
property. As a property, it is a source of financial gain, personal
satisfaction, sense of security and social prestige for individuals.
For groups, land acquires meanings of cultural territory and serves as
a symbol of belonging together (4). Only a small proportion of urban
residents possess land, though a vast majority entertain a consuming
desire to acquire it. The ownership of land (and buildings)
distinguishes propertied classes from renters, upper and middle
classes from the poor and in Europe and America even the working class
from the dispossessed minorities. A land tenure system sustains and in
turn is maintained by the social structure.
Urban land is a unique possession. Unlike other forms of property,
the ownership of urban land confers considerably restrained rights of
use and profit, even in capitalist countries. The use of urban land is
not a matter of owner's choice alone. One has to abide by zoning and
building restrictions and in many countries, even capital gains from
enhanced value arising from authorized change of use are taxed away.
The ownership of urban land is a very circumscribed possession. It is
regulated by public interest and is now being increasingly treated as
a community resource.
It is a fact that almost every new use of urban land in most Western
cities proceeds with the permission of public authorities. Local and
regional governments are the arbiters of how a parcel of land is to be
used, built upon and developed. These public powers are not arbitrary
but they are meant to safeguard a community's health, welfare and
economy. The rationale for such a strong public presence in the
process of urban land disposition lies in the mutual externalities
cast among land uses (5). The social and economic interdependence of
activities imprint a corresponding interrelation on land sites. Thus
activities supported by one land parcel enhance or reduce the
usability of others and vice versa. A glue factory in a residential
area casts negative externalities whereas a park enhances the
livability of an area. Such mutual effects are not only economically
crucial but also have bearing on the public health and common weal. As
the negative effects were first to be recognized, the public interest
found initial expression in zoning and building regulations. Gradually
the public interest in urban land has embraced concerns of efficiency,
economy, fiscal viability, equity and now environmental protection of
an urban area. These concerns have brought into play new instruments
of public intervention, e.g. betterment taxes, impact
assessments, land policies, etc. They have also turned the process of
urban land development and disposition into a complex interplay of
public and private actors, thereby redefining the concept of ownership
for urban land.
So far we have broadly reviewed the economic and institutional
significance of urban land. The picture emerging in this description
suggests that land considerations interpose into almost every aspect
of urban life. They may not be the only factor determining the
well-being of a city but appropriate land policies are necessary to
bring about prosperity and equity. The contemporary accounts of urban
problems reveal the pervasiveness of land issues.
What is popularly known as the urban crisis is a catchword for a host
of problems. It is comprised of housing shortage, transportation
deficiencies, environmental degradation, unsanitary living conditions,
insufficient and unhealthy water supply, sprawled development, rising
land prices, increasing fiscal deficits, shortage of developed land,
political fragmentation, in- and out-migration of income classes, etc.
These are intertwined issues, though land problems stand out as a
common denominator. The high costs of land development and the
inappropriate use of developed land inhibit the housing supply. A
disorderly pattern of land use elongates journeys to work and causes
transportation congestions. Low density and sprawled-out development
at the urban periphery exact heavy social costs in the form of
uneconomical expenditures on public facilities, wasteful use of land
and absence of a sense of community. The economy of a city depends
upon facilitating of operations of interdependencies through
appropriate land use patterns. Similarly, social justice within a city
cannot be realized in the face of persistent geographic inequities of
public facilities and services. What is striking about these issues is
that they require a socially efficient pattern of land use and an
equitable system of land tenure. An analysis of each of these issues
brings out the necessity of regulating and guiding the land
disposition process in the communal interest. Henry George may have
been over-enthusiastic about the role of land in the wealth of
nations, but he was not mistaken in holding that land issues permeate
every aspect of a community's life.
Two conclusions emerge from the foregoing discussion, (a) The process
of land disposition has very significant influence on the urban
economy and on communal welfare, (b) The use of a parcel of urban land
has bearing on the usability of neighboring sites. This characteristic
makes urban land a community resource.
With this brief review of the role of land in an urban system, I now
come to the question: What are the significant attributes of urban
land and how do they arise? This question takes us into an exploration
of the nature of urban land.
II: WHAT IS URBAN LAND?
THIS QUESTION is not as trivial as it may appear at first. A moment's
reflection will begin to reveal its relevance as well as its
complexity. To say that urban land is the land falling within urban
boundaries only begs the question. Boundaries of cities may or may not
have been set on any functional criteria. Often they are the outcome
of historical accidents and political convenience. And contemporary
metropolises cannot even be said to have precise boundaries. Mere
areal extent is a very ambiguous criterion to define urban land. It
would leave out such obvious urban uses as housing subdivisions and
industrial estates around a city and include farms falling within the
city boundaries. Urban land would be more appropriately denned by
functional criteria.
The land which is used or expected to be used for urban activities
may be defined as urban land. This definition shifts the focus from
where on the surface of the earth a piece of land is situated to what
goes on upon, under or over it. The latter emphasis has fewer
ambiguities and less arbitrariness. By making activities as the
criterion determining 'urbanness' of land, its functional aspects are
emphasized. Ratcliff, Smith, among others have also defined land in
functional terms (7). This approach points towards social and economic
factors as the primary determinants of urban land. They lay bases of
what constitutes urban activities at a point in time. What use a
parcel of land will support is the prime determinant of its value and
role as urban land. The process of settling of uses on land parcels is
the mode of making urban land. To understand the nature of urban land,
we must identify attributes by which urban land is characterized.
III: ATTRIBUTES OF URBAN LAND
URBAN LAND comes into being when a piece of the earth's surface
becomes eligible for urban uses. It is a passive process in the sense
that 'eligibility' comes from without and settles on the land. Little
changes physically in the land involved and often little is done to
make it usable for specific urban use. Neighborhood as well as city
wide externalities and public investments are prime factors in
endowing a land parcel with urban usability. The workings of these
processes do not concern me presently. They will be discussed later. A
more pressing need at the moment is to identify the outcome of this
process. What attributes does this process endow upon land to make it
a valuable urban property? It appears that the following attributes
are the distinguishing characteristics of urban land.
(a)
Location: This is the single most distinguishing attribute of
urban land. Location means the position of a parcel of land in
relation to other sites supporting complementary economic and social
activities. Generally, it is expressed in terms of accessibility of
one site to another. It may be noted that the bases of location are a
set of economic relationships, which means that it is a relational
concept. Yet it has come to be used in absolute terms also, in the
sense that one parcel of land has more or less locational potential
than others, or more commonly it is said to have greater or lesser
accessibility. Accessibility is rooted in economic, social and
technological interdependencies of activities. As a concept, it is
appropriate to talk about accessibility between houses and work places
because they harbor interrelated activities. Whereas the accessibility
between houses and jails seldom concerns anyone (except specialists in
inmate rehabilitation). Thus, it is the mutual complementarity of
activities which lays the framework of activities and determines
locational pulls of land parcels. These interlinkages are facilitated
or hindered by roads, paths, telecommunication lines, etc., which are
public goods of one kind or another. They require public investment
and collective action to be produced. This means that location is an
externally denned characteristic, however looked upon, whether as a
function of interdependencies of activities or as a manifestation of
facility of communication and transportation between two sites.
(b) Space: The term land truly refers to three-dimensional
space. The height is not a uniformly similar dimension for all urban
land parcels. It varies from zone to zone according to local
regulations. One parcel of land may be built over up to three stories
while on another a 20-story building might be raised. Such zoning
regulations introduce wide variation in the amount of space available
at different sites. That is why height is an important dimension of
urban land.
Another reason for treating urban land explicitly as space is that
often a so-called parcel of land may not even be grounded on the
surface of the earth. A specified layer of space is all that it may
mean. For example, a third floor apartment in a condominium tower is
an urban land parcel which exists as a layer of space. This means that
urban land is a product of man-made rules and technology as much as it
is nature's creation in the form of the earth's surface and
surrounding atmosphere.
The human hand is also evident in surveying, mapping, registration
and subdivision of space. Similarly, the technology of high rise
buildings make the use of the vertical dimension feasible. These
legal, institutional and technological instruments parcel out space
and create the resource called urban land.
(c) Property: Urban land (the term refers to space from here
on) is also a tangible possession of individuals and corporations. Yet
it is an unusual possession in the sense that owners cannot exhaust or
carry it away. It is there for their use and it will be there long
after the present set of owners is gone. The proprietorship of land
consists of a bundle of rights: rights to use, sell, bequeath, profit
and exclude others, alienate, assimilate, etc. (8). The market
transactions of land are dealings in these rights. It must be
mentioned that these rights have been modified and constrained
extensively in modern times. This also means that property is not
comprised of the same rights everywhere. These features of urban land
as property have two implications. First, urban land as a property
confers some decision-making powers upon owners for its use.
Therefore, motives guiding these decisions become important
determinants of land uses. Secondly, as a property, urban land also
becomes a repository of investments for capital gains. In this
context, urban land is subject to different objectives and its
disposition is guided by considerations of investment markets. Often
the role of urban land as an investment could conflict with its
function as a site for urban activities. It introduces tensions and
affects the land disposition process (9).
(d) Clustering: Physically, there are no free-standing units
of land, a tiny island being the only exception. All land is
contiguous. As Cho says "Land is like a seamless garment, it
exists as a unity - any part of it, with the heat and light, the air
and moisture which nature assigned to it, is not easily separable from
other parts" (10). Yet it is carved out in proprietary parcels.
The phenomenon of land subdivision is essentially a legal and
institutional mechanism to portion out land surface among owners and
users. It does not affect the physical contiguity. But man has learned
to suppress the fact of contiguity and look upon a parcel of land as a
free-standing unit. For agricultural uses the fiction of the
autonomous land unit is valid to a large extent. Each farm is a
relatively free-standing production unit. In urban settings, this
fiction gives way to the notion of interdependence of land uses and
parcels. Urban land parcels are inseparably bound together. They occur
in clusters. The physical contiguity lays ground for the network of
interrelations which bind clusters together.
The clustering of urban land parcels has two aspects. One, a
quantitative agglomeration of land uses (a minimum number of a sort)
must exist to earn the designation of urban land for constituent
parcels. A non-farm dwelling in the country or a single gas station on
a back road is seldom regarded as a unit of urban land. Secondly,
clustering as an attribute also refers to the interlinkages among land
parcels. It suggests that each parcel is an anchor for one element of
a system of activities. The web of externalities is once again
evident.
As an attribute of urban land, clustering reflects the communal
nature of the urban system. It implies that community facilities,
local regulations, etc., must pre-exist for urban land to come into
being. It suggests that urban land is not merely a slice of the
earth's surface, it is also an element of a system of sites. This
systematic aspect of urban land needs to be grasped.
(e) Heterogeneity: Urban land is a very heterogeneous
commodity. There is a high degree of uniqueness among land parcels
arising from varying incidence of one or more determining
characteristics, i.e. location, size, shape or form of space,
tenure, etc. Uniqueness as an attribute of urban land arises from, as
Ratcliff perceived, a "complex but singular set of relationships
that one parcel has with other parcels" (11). These relationships
are embedded in social and economic activities centered on these
parcels. Apart from these combinations of inter-dependencies, land
parcels acquire uniqueness from wide variations of size, shape,
tenure, etc.
The significance of heterogeneity as an attribute lies in the fact
that it tends to lend a monopolistic character to land markets (12).
It makes land relatively impervious to economic laws of supply and
demand and it alters assumptions about the operation of land markets.
It is all the more important to recognize that uniqueness of
individual parcels and their monopolistic character arise from
situational and contextual factors and it is not the product of an
entrepreneur's inventiveness.
Heterogeneity of urban land results in highly insukr submarkets,
whose prices and uses are not transferable. This calls for strong
public intervention to ensure appropriate use of unique parcels and to
safeguard interdependencies of activities.
(f) Immobility and Indestructibility: These are physical
attributes of land which are fully characteristic of urban land.
Obviously a parcel of land cannot be transported anywhere else. It is
fixed to the surface of the earth. This also means that an excess of
urban land at one place cannot make up for a shortage at another. In
the same vein, land as two-dimensional space cannot be either
physically created or destroyed: urban land reclaimed from swamp land
is made usable. A use does not exhaust land resources; it only ties
them up for a long period of time. If the use should be removed, the
land still remains. It is particularly true in urban settings, where
any changes in the physical characteristics of land as a result of the
use do not significantly reduce the opportunities of subsequent uses.
Turner observes that: "The land market is unusual in that it is
essentially a second hand market. The product is one which generally
has been used before in its existing developed form and the new
product is the exception rather than the rule" (13).
What picture emerges from these attributes of urban land? To put it
succinctly, urban land is a bundle of locational possibilities derived
from activities and facilities surrounding a land parcel. The
essential features of urban land are man-made, with nature providing
the stage upon which these possibilities and rights are enacted.
Undoubtedly nature sets the limit within which man-made
characteristics operate, but these constraints, historically, have not
proven to be insurmountable. By and large, urban land uses have been
determined by economic and technological considerations, though the
neglect of consideration of nature has not been without social costs,
as environmentalists have begun to point out.
From the-foregoing discussion, the following six propositions can be
abstracted.
- a. The distinguishing characteristics of urban land arise from
its being drawn into a system of activities. A parcel of land is
intrinsically a passive factor in the process of its
transformation to urban uses. The determinants of uses originate
from without.
- b. Urban land as a unit of space and property is rooted in
legal, administrative and economic institutions.
- c. With numerous institutional and technological variables
bearing upon urban land, it tends to be a heterogeneous commodity.
There is a high degree of uniqueness in individual land parcels
which contributes towards monopolistic tendencies in the market.
- d. Given the systematic nature of urban land, much of its value
can be ascribed to public investments, institutional decisions and
economic interdependencies.
- e. Urban land is a resource whose allocation and use have
direct bearing on the public interest.
- f. Urban land is both a utility good and a commercial good.
These two uses of land, many times, conflict with each other. One
promotes utility and the other delivers profits.
The viewpoint presented above does not reflect a consensual position
about the nature of urban land. Although each of the above
propositions would be acceptable with some reservations to a majority
of observers of the urban scene, their overall message would be
resisted by many, often on thinly disguised ideological grounds.
Land has always stirred passionate controversies and the present era
is not an exception. With the emergence of cities as centers of
economic and political power, urban land becomes an object of
contention. Who may own? What rights may owners have? How much public
control is necessary? Who may benefit from windfalls of increasing
values? These questions now divide national opinions. The depth and
persistence of these divisions are pointedly illustrated by the
British experience. Labour and Conservative parties in Britain are on
the opposite sides of the ideological spectrum on the issue of urban
land. One supports public ownership of development rights and promotes
taking away of value increases arising from change of use. The other
maintains faith in the individual's rights of owning and profiting
from land. A Labour government institutes measures to extend the
public domain in urban land; whereas the Conservatives, on coming to
power, roll back such measures. This see-saw for and against
betterment taxes and community land ownership has gone on in Britain
since 1947 (14). If practitioners of democratic politics have such
passionate views about urban land, it can be imagined how fierce will
be academic battles on issues of ownership and use. Obviously for a
discussion of the nature of urban land to remain dispassionate is an
unlikely event. Any view, no matter how analytically arrived at, is
likely to be met with objections from the right or the left and
perhaps from both. This is also true for the viewpoint developed
above. In order to offer a taste of different philosophic positions, I
will give a brief resume of three schools of thought about the nature
of urban land. These positions are not clearly articulated in the
literature. They have been gleaned from respective land rent theories
and from assumptions underlying various modelling exercises.
IV: MAJOR SCHOOLS OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT AND URBAN LAND
a.
Neo-classical: The major thrust of the neo-classical
conception of urban land lies in treating it as a commodity which is
governed by microeconomic laws of supply and demand. Its supply is
assumed to be a function of costs of accessibility and its demand is
prompted by feasibility of putting a use to it. This is how
contemporary neo-classicists make land markets subservient to
competition between utility and costs. Accessibility is the key to
their formulations. It introduces cost of producing urban land-thus
doing away with the dilemma of the gift of nature and becomes the
basis of competition among uses seeking to settle on land. One of the
consequences of this formulation is that land loses its special
status. Its supply becomes relatively elastic and its utility
variable. In sum, it is turned into a commodity conforming to
assumptions of homogeneity and substitutibility. Alonso's rent bid
curves and Wingo's postulate of complementarity between transport
costs and land values portray urban land as a substitutible commodity
and invest it with a fair degree of homogeneity (IS). Ely and Wehrwein
have mentioned in passing that immobility is not a barrier to the
treatment of urban land as an economic good. They argue that it is the
use that is an important attribute of land and that is perfectly
mobile (16). Marshall himself was not ready to concede a special role
to land as a gift of nature and as a factor of fixed supply. He argued
that land is a form of capital, fixed in supply in the short run but a
variable in the long run, though he also conceded that land earned
quasi-rent for its limited supply (17).
Neo-classical theorists are silent about neighborhood externalities,
the role of public investments in endowing usability and accessibility
to land and the tenurial variations as determinants of urban land
characteristics. By stressing the quantifiable parameters of
accessibility (transport costs), they turn the locational potential of
land into a continuous variable. This makes land a homogeneous
commodity and divests it (in their eyes) of monopolistic
characteristics - conditions necessary to maintain a neo-classical
stance. Yet there are so many exceptions to these assumptions that an
observer of urban land cannot help regarding it a lumpy, heterogeneous
good. This is one reason that most land economists are
institutionalists.
b. Institutionalists: In order to describe the
institutionalists' views about the nature of urban land, a few words
about institutionalism as an approach are in order, because it is a
relatively less known mode of analysis. Institutionalists give an
equal emphasis to organizations and rules through which economic
behavior is mediated. Unlike neo-classicists, they assume that
abstract laws of demand and supply are only one of the elements of
economic behavior. Arrangements through which these laws find
expression affect their outcome to such a degree that those laws must
be treated as variables in economic analysis. In simple terms, it
means that economic analysis should not be limited to the abstract
forces of demand and supply, but it should embrace the sociopolitical
settings which prompt and enact economic decisions. Recently Ratcliff
has articulated some premises of institutionalism and advocated the
continuation of the institutional approach in land economics because
by analyzing institutions, remedial policies for urban ills can be
devised (18).
The institutionalists look upon urban land as the product of a series
of public and private decisions. It is an economic good embedded in
social and political institutions and, thus, inseparable from them
even conceptually. Location is also an important attribute of urban
land for institutionalists, but they ascribe it to a multitude of
factors including accessibility, but not limited to it. The locational
potential of land parcels arises from sociological preferences, public
regulations and, most of all, by neighborhood externalities. Clawson
thus describes the nature of urban land: "The use and value of
each piece of urban land is largely determined by activities on other
tracts of land within the same urban area" (19).
Institutionalists are also well aware of property as an attribute of
urban land and they assign considerable weight to tenurial features
and public regulations in assessing the economic potential of land
parcels. These features neo-classicists dismiss as contextual elements
whereas institutional land economists take them to be the
distinguishing features of land as a commodity (20).
It might be noticed that my description of the nature of urban land
follows the institutional approach. This is both a tribute to long
validated ideas of land economists and a recognition of the empirical
relevance of institutionalism.
c. Marxian: Urban land does not figure in Marx's writings
directly. Yet the Marxian mode of analysis can be fruitfully applied
to urban land issues. David Harvey is an acknowledged contemporary
interpreter of the Marxists' position on urban issues. I will
paraphrase his views to outline the Marxian definition of the nature
of urban land.
Harvey uses the Marxian distinction between 'use value' and 'exchange
value' of commodities to flush out attributes of urban land. He argues
that land as a commodity takes on different characteristics depending
on which of the two values is dominant in a situation. This also means
that their contradiction makes land a paradoxical object. He abstracts
six such characteristics.
- i. Land has a fixed location and, thus, a person who determines
the use of a site has monopoly privileges.
- ii. Land is a commodity which no individual can do without.
- iii. Urban land in different sectors takes on the commodity
form (i.e. salable goods) to varying degrees. In business
and in the owner-occupied housing sector, its use value is more
dominant, whereas in the rental sector, land takes on the
commodity form more frequently.
- iv. In a capitalist economy an individual has a dual interest
in property: as a current and future use value and as potential or
actual exchange value.
- v. Land is bought with a large outlay at one point in time and
used over a long period. This means that financial institutions
play a very important role in the land market of capitalist
society.
- vi. Land has different uses: providing shelter, space, privacy,
location, wealth, etc. Not all these uses are equally desired by
every household. Thus the capacity of land to satisfy needs and
deliver use value depends as much on its intrinsic qualities as
upon the type of user. Potentials of land and user's motives
interpenetrate (21).
The Marxian view of the nature of urban land, as interpreted above,
refines and extends the institutionalists' logic. It assigns
'property' the decisive position engendering monopoly in land markets.
Locational differentiation may make land a heterogeneous commodity,
but individual ownership exploits these unique features through
monopolistic practices. Similarly, by pointing out that users have
widely varying demands on land, it is noted that location is only one
of a multitude of contending influences in land markets. This
introduces another set of determinants of land uses and values - i.e.
user's motives. Yet land is needed by everyone to live on,
irrespective of other overlaid motives for possessing it. These
contradictions and dilemmas are inherent in the nature of land. Thus,
the linearity of the neo-classical models contrasts with the
circularity of the Marxian formulations.
Among the three, the institutionalist and the Marxian approaches have
many points of congruence. Both assign social and political
underpinnings of urban land significant weight, whereas the
neo-classicists lay stress on economic variables, to the virtual
exclusion of any other. Neo-classicists are caught on the horns of a
dilemma about land. They would like to treat it as any other
commodity, but its immobility and fixed supply and its role as a
factor of production cannot be overlooked. Institutional and Marxian
approaches treat land as an uncommon good and assume it to be a
heterogeneous commodity. A brief look at how this heterogeneity arises
will help clarify the point.
V: SOCIAL ECONOMY OF URBAN LAND
THE MAIN UTILITY of urban land is as a site for human activities. It
is a paradox of urban land that one parcel of land along the main
street may become a choice commercial site, whereas the other side of
the same block, fronting on an equally wide street, may languish for
want of demand. Within a few yards of each other in a downtown
section, one parcel of land is a skid row and the other provides
fashionable addresses. The question is, what creates such locational
differentiations? Answers to this question will also explain the bases
of heterogeneity of land, yet they are hard to come by. Confessedly,
one can say that little is known about these micro-variations. We have
a better idea of the larger picture from negative exponential curves
of land use intensities and values (22). The concentric zone model of
Park and Burgess, and the sector theory of Homer Hoyt also describe a
general picture.
These theories have been challenged but even if they were acceptable
in their entirety, they do not explain the high degree of
differentiation. Accessibility as an explanatory variable fails to
explain contrasts in desirability of the two sides of a city block.
Why is there such a wide-! spread housing abandonment in prime
locations of American cities? Why do inaccessible sections continue to
be thriving commercial centers? Why do infiltrations of migrants drive
down property values? These paradoxes underline the institutional,
historical and social factors in the making of urban land. What goes
around a parcel of land, what externalities, and what symbolic and
cultural values pervade in a situation? These are the factors that
need to be examined to explain such paradoxes.
House lots fronting on a park may benefit from its amenity, if the
park is crime-free; otherwise it may be a value-reducing nuisance.
Here is an example of social externalities which has strong influence
on the usability of nearby urban land. It illustrates how special
conditions and local services - police for example - influence the use
of land. This is not a unique example. Such cases can be cited over
and over again.
The gentrification of inner city neighborhoods (23); the popularity
of preservationists' causes; the disenchantment with suburbia; the
rising price of motor fuels are examples of how social trends continue
to redefine the locational potentials of city land. These examples
illustrate the point that usability, hence value, of urban land is
determined by many factors and merely focusing on economic variables -
still worse a single variable - is an untenable approach.
Accessibility lays the groundwork for social and economic forces to
operate. It provides a coarse grain description of urban spatial
structure. That is as far as it can take the land economist. Any
attempt to understand and influence the basis of the urban land market
realistically would require a broader socio-economic mode of analysis.
A larger range of variables will have to be dealt with, even at the
cost of elegance and quantification. In sum, urban land can be better
understood by following an approach described as that of social
economy. This statement calls for an elaboration.
Social economy is not a formalized discipline or branch of a
discipline. At best, it can be described as an approach to analyzing
economic issues in which psychological, sociological and cultural
factors are given adequate weight. This is in contrast to the usual
economic analysis wherein the organizational and valuational
parameters of economic behavior are assumed to be either irrelevant or
insignificant. Whether a commodity is produced and supplied by a
monastic order or a business firm, conventional economics is
unconcerned with its mode of production. Positive economics focuses
upon quantities, cost and demand, etc., of commodities regardless of
how they come into being. Yet there has been a streak in economic
thought which lays stress on giving attention to the social
relationships in which production and distributional processes are
embedded. Galbraith is a contemporary practitioner of this
methodology. The mode of analysis which looks at the social causes of
economic behavior and also examines the social consequences of
economic process has been called 'Social Economies' (24). In a recent
book entitled
The Social Economy of Cities, the subject matter has been
defined as 'the interrelationship of the social and economic systems
operating within ... a particular urban place' (25).
The preceding discussion points out that urban land is a product of
institutional and social arrangements. Under varying arrangements,
urban land will acquire significantly different characteristics. That
is why the phenomenon of urban land has to be examined in the context
of a sociolegal framework.
The questions that need to be raised in investigating urban land are:
(i) what are the various institutional forms through which urban land
is disposed and produced; (ii) how these arrangements affect the
supply, pricing, allocation and pattern of use of urban land; and
(iii) how the emerging patterns of use and pricing affect economy,
efficiency and equity of a city. These questions constitute primary
concerns of the social economy of urban land and they must be dealt
with in formulating land policies.
We have discovered that externalities, both social and economic, have
a significant part in determining the usability of urban land. By and
large, they endow a parcel of land with characteristics that make it a
valuable urban site. These externalities take many forms. They may be
the spill-over of neighboring activities, or indivisible benefits (or
costs) derived from public goods, such as roads, facilities and
services, etc., and from the social environment. Even its
accessibility can be treated as an externality arising from the
presence of interdependent activities and a transport network. The
pre-eminence of externalities as determinants of the 'nature' of urban
land has been identified by Clawson, Neutze and Smith, three
contemporary analysts of American urban land markets (26). It is,
therefore, necessary that any analysis of the potential for use of an
urban site must begin with an assessment of various externalities.
The role of the community in investing land with urban
characteristics has been widely recognized in European city planning
practices. For example, Britain treats the development of land, which
effectively means changing the use, as a public prerogative. An
individual can be allowed to do so, if it conforms to public plans. It
also exacts from individual owners a share from any increase in value
due to development (27). France, Sweden and the Netherlands have
equally stringent regulations safeguarding communal interests in urban
land. In the United States, the public interest has been
institutionalized in the form of zoning and planning regulations to
safeguard health and welfare. Zoning boards have constraining powers
over individuals' use of land. These are accepted modifications of the
private ownership of land, even in capitalist societies. They show the
degree to which community interests have been acknowledged to be
inseparable components of urban land. These are empirical facts which
speak for themselves. The disposition of urban land calls, for
safeguarding community interests so that the overall pattern of land
use and distribution of land values accords with goals of economy,
equity and welfare. Darin-Drabkin calls these considerations aspects
of land's social utility and regards them as the necessary criteria
for guiding urban land markets (28). So have many others, from Henry
George to Mason Gaffney.
Urban land is also property in capitalist and mixed economy
countries. There is individual ownership of land parcels, though what
the ownership entails varies considerably. Urban land in these two
conflicting roles - community resource and property - is a source of
tension. On the one hand, it keeps the question of who benefits and
who pays for the creation of urban characteristics on the forefront of
the political agenda; on the other, it turns the land development and
allocation process into a complex interplay of private and public
decisions, actors and organizations (29). The policy making process
has to mediate among these conflicting claims. Any proposals for land
use have to deal with the financial consequences of the intended
changes and ensure equity between the public and private interests and
among the various individual owners.
The sum total of the above stated conclusions is that urban land does
not satisfy the usual assumptions about the nature of economic goods,
i.e., homogeneity, divisibility (30). Its valued
characteristics are communally produced and its disposition is being
guided by collective interests. These findings set urban land apart
from normal economic commodities. To it, the textbook micro-economic
principles are not applicable even probabilistically. Its supply is
limited and lumpy, its demand unceasing and its utility fundamental to
human existence. Production and allocation of urban land must proceed
at least like other public goods, in accordance with the ideological
preferences of a country.
NOTES AND REFERENCES
- Walter Isard, An
Introduction to Regional Science (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall, 1975), Chap. 1.
- Eric E. Lampard, "The
History of Cities in the Economically Advanced Areas," in
John Friedmann and William Alonso, eds., Regional Development
and Planning (Cambridge: The M.I.T. Press, 1964), pp. 321-42.
- The term 'resource' here means
a scarce good which helps produce other goods and resources. (G.
Bannock, et al., The Penguin Dictionary of Economics,
Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1972), p. 352. The older term, 'natural
resources,' signified the provisions of nature. See B. J. Horton,
Dictionary of Modern Economics (Washington: Public Affairs
Press, 1948), p. 237.
- Walter Farey, Land Use in
Central Boston (Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 1947).
- Externalities are such costs
or benefits of an act of consumption or production which fall on
others and which are not transactions in a market. Garbage burning
in a backyard is a negative externality on neighbors, whereas a
hedge of rose bushes may be a positive externality.
- Barbara Ward, The Home of
Man (Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1976), pp. 39-59.
- Richard U. Ratcliff, Urban
Land Economics (New York: McGraw-Hill Book Co., Inc., 1949),
pp. 1-18, 280-301; Wallace F. Smith, Land Using Activities
(Berkeley: University of California Center for Real Estate and
Urban Economics, 1970), p. 51.
- V. Kruse, The Right of
Property (London: Oxford Univ. Press, 1939), Chap. 6.
- Haim Darin-Drabkin, Land
Policy and Urban Growth (London: Pergamon Press, 1977), Chap.
8.
- Joe H. Cho, 'Externalities and
Land Economics,' Land Economics, p. 68.
- Ratcliff, op. cit., p.
284.
- Darin-Drabkin, op. cit.,
p. 178.
- D. M. Turner, An Approach
to Land Values (Berkhamsted: Geographical Publications Ltd.,
1977), p. 39.
- D. R. Denman, "Land
Policies: The Sowers and the Scythemen" in Stanley Millward,
ed., Urban Harvest (Berkhamsted: Geographical Publications
Ltd., 1977), pp. 23-38.
- W. Alonso, 'A Theory of the
Urban Land Market,' Papers and Proceedings of the Regional
Science Association, Vol. 6, 1960, pp. 154-59; L. Wingo, Transportation
and Land Use (Washington: Resources for the Future, Inc.,
1961), pp. 63-80.
- Richard T. Ely and George S.
Wehrwein, Land Economics (Madison: Univ. of Wisconsin
Press, 1964), pp. 54-55.
- Alfred Marshall, Principles
of Economics, 8th edition (London: Macmillan & Co.,
reprinted in 1964), pp. 349-76.
- Ratcliff identifies four
elements of the institutional approach, i.e. (i) problem oriented;
(ii) concern with human economic motives; (iii) interdisciplinary
in approach; (iv) focus on institutions as material of analysis
and seeking ways of changing them. R. Ratcliff: 'Institutionalism
and Urban Economies' in Michael A. Goldberg, ed., Recent
Perspectives in Urban Land Economics (Vancouver: University of
British Columbia, 1976), p. 5.
- Marion Clawson, America's
Land and Its Uses (Washington: Resources for the Future,
1972), p. 43.
- Ratcliff, op. cit.,
pp. 5-6.
- David Harvey, Social
Justice and the City (London: Edward Arnold, 1973), pp.
157-60.
- Colin Clark, Population
Growth and Land Use (London: Macmillan, 1969), pp. 339-85.
- James Pitt, Gentrification
in Islington (London: Peoples Forum, 1977).
- W. Hagenbuch, Social
Economics (New York: Columbia Univ. Press, 1958), pp. 2-7. See
also Economics and Sociology: Towards an Integration, T.
Huppes, ed. (Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Social Sciences Division,
1976). This approach is in some ways similar to, and in others
different from that of Adolph Lowe. For his conception of "political
economics" as a 'science,' see his Economics and
Sociology: A Plea for Cooperation in the Social Sciences
(London: Alien & Unwin, 1935) and particularly his On
Economic Knowledge (New York: Harper & Row, 1965) (but
compare his Towards a Science of Political Economics, in
R. L. Heilbroner, ed., Economic Means and Social Ends,
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1969) and his The Path
of Economic Growth (New York: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1976),
pp. 14-16 and 286.
- Gary Gappert and Harold M.
Rose, eds., The Social Economy of Cities,/i> (Beverly
Hills: Sage Publications, 1975), p. 7.
- Marion Clawson, Suburban
Land Conversion in the United States (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
Univ. Press, 1971); Max Neutze, The Suburban Apartment Boom
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press, 1968); Wallace Smith, Urban
Development (Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 1975).
- Marion Clawson and Peter Hall,
Planning and Urban Growth (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univ.
Press, 1973), pp. 160-64.
- Darin-Drabkin, op. cit.,
p. 120.
- Clawson, Suburban Land
Conversion etc., op. cit.
- Alfred W. Stonier and Douglas
C. Hague, A Textbook of Economic Theory (London: Longmans,
Green and Co., 1965), p. 11.
|